André Béteille and Alexis de Tocqueville

 

                                         ALAN MACFARLANE

 

[From Institutions and Inequalities; Essays in Honour of André Béteille (Oxford Univ. Press, Delhi, 1999), eds. Ramachandra Guha and Jonathan P.Parry]

 

 

p.284

 

There is an old Chinese saying that it is unlikely to be a fish that

discovered water or a bird that discovered air. Most of us live in a

world where we take our culture as 'natural', and seldom more so

than in relation to the ideology and actual distribution of rank and power.

Occasionally, however, a dramatic change or set of contrasts leads one or

more thinkers to question these basic and largely unquestioned assumptions.

One famous occasion was in the eighteenth-century Enlightenment when,

for example in the work of John Millar, Adam Ferguson and Jean Jacques

Rousseau and others a systematic analysis of equality and inequality was

undertaken.

 

     Another formidable attempt to understand equality and inequality was

made by Alexis de Tocqueville (1805-58). There were a number of conditions

which seem to have played an important part in directing Tocqueville's

attention to the question of equality and which gave his analysis an unusual

depth. First there was his family background. An aristocratic pedigree

contrasted with an upbringing within a post-Revolutionary France formally

dedicated to equality and the abolition of privileged ranks. Then there were

his travels from a land so recently hierarchical to the most dramatically free

and equal civilization in the world, America, as well as to England. Finally

there were the revolutionary changes in France itself, as an inegalitarian system

tried to adapt to the new ideology of equality. All this made equality his

obsession and his life's work was concerned with trying to reconcile liberty

and equality. He was a man divided between two worlds, caught in an endless

struggle between his head and his heart. As he put it in a discarded note,

there were standing against each other 'Mon Instinct, Mes Opinions'. 'I have

an intellectual taste for democratic institutions, but I am an aristocrat by

instinct . . .' (Drescher 1964: 15). Out of this clash emerged his great works

on Democracy in America and the Ancien Regime.

 

     It is attractive to see Andre Beteille as someone in a similar position,

reflecting deeply on the essence of equality and inequality partly because of

 

 

285

 

his personal circumstances, partly through the changing and contrasting world

he experienced. With his French father and Indian mother, Beteille is an heir

to diverse philosophies and traditions. I As an academic who never permanently

left India, yet frequently spent periods in Europe and America, he is deeply

aware of the contrasts of 'East' and 'West'. As someone who participated in

the rapid changes in India over the period since Independence, he could see

the battle of ideologies based on inequality and equality on his own doorstep.

It is thus no surprise to find that his lifelong obsession has been with equality

and inequality. His Ph.D. thesis was published under the title of Caste, Class

and Power; Changing Patterns of Stratification in a Tanjore Village (1965)

and was soon followed by his influential edited set of readings

on Social Inequality (1969), and then by Inequality among Men (1977) and The Idea

of Natural Inequality and Other Essays (1983).

 

    There is not merely a resemblance between these two thinkers. There is

clearly a very great amount of continuity. In some ways Beteille can be seen

as one of the heirs of Tocqueville, as someone who has applied Tocqueville's

earlier insights and broadened and updated his analysis. His debt and the

way in which his work complements Tocqueville's can be seen if we consider

first some of his explicit comments on Tocqueville's writings and the way in

which they provide a framework for his own comparative analysis.

 

THE FIRST DISTINCTION: HIERARCHICAL AND

EGALITARIAN SYSTEMS

 

As a first step, Beteille follows Tocqueville in proposing a simple binary

model in space and time which suggests that until the eighteenth century all

the world was based on the premise of natural inequality, but after that western

Europe and America moved rapidly to the premise of natural equality, leaving

India and much of Asia to 'catch up' later. It can also be shown in certain

parts of Beteille's earlier work. Let us briefly examine this use of Tocqueville's

ideas and the way Beteille proposes an initial binary opposition between two

systems of equality. Beteille wrote that

 

For Tocqueville there were two kinds of societies, aristocratic society with its fixed

and stable hierarchy of estates or castes, and democratic society which allowed or

even encouraged the free movement of individuals across its classes. Aristocratic

societies prevailed in Europe prior to the nineteenth century; and America in the

first half of that century was the best example of democratic society. (1983: 39)

 

Beteille reiterates the contrast many times.

 

The first feature that strikes us is that the major civilisations of the past were all

hierarchical by design, although the logic of the hierarchy was not everywhere the

same. The design was most elaborately and consistently worked out in the case of

traditional India, although it was very much in evidence in medieval Europe and also

in China from the time of Confucius onwards. (1977: 25)

 

 

 

286

 

Thus until the eighteenth century, all the world was 'hierarchical'.

 

It is not as if the principle of hierarchy enjoyed legitimacy only in traditional Indian

society; in this matter India was not unique among the civilisations of the past. In pre-

industrial Europe also society was not only divided into unequal ranks., orders or

estates, but these divisions were broadly accepted in principle. There also the social

hierarchy was invested with a measure of unity and coherence so that what existed

was considered to be by and large right, proper and desirable. (Ibid.: 150)

 

Beteille shows how this was elaborated in relation to the legal structure.

 

As is well known, feudal society in Europe was divided into estates. This division did

not just exist as a fact of experience, it was supported by legal sanctions. The same

laws did not apply to all, and there were separate courts to deal with cases relating to

persons of different estates; for a person of a superior estate to be tried in an inferior

court would have been a violation of honour. (Ibid.: 43)

 

It was enshrined in the value system.

 

The civilizations of Europe and Asia were in pre-modern times marked by the

prominence of ranked social divisions and by the attention paid to rank in the various

spheres of life. The attention to rank was carried over into legal rules and religious

beliefs which are in such societies closely intertwined. Moreover, as Tocqueville points

out, different standards of right conduct and different conceptions of honour, virtue

and even morality are associated with the different ranks or orders into which society

is divided. (1983: 56-7)

 

According to Beteille, all this changed in the West somewhere between the

mid-eighteenth and mid-nineteenth centuries. The timing of this revolutionary

change also gives us a clue as to the causes of the dramatic shift.

 

Many things contributed to the kinds of change which Tocqueville and others

witnessed and foresaw. Foremost among these were the Industrial Revolution and

the French Revolution which both began in the second half of the eighteenth century.

They set about in a hundred different ways to destroy the material as well as the

moral foundations of the traditional social order with its old hierarchies and myths.

In Europe people were not only being imbued with new aspirations, but new

opportunities were being created by and for them on an unprecedented scale.

(1977: 147)

 

It is a familiar story and one which has deeply influenced sociological thought:

the birth of the 'modem' in the West, separating off a certain part of the

globe from the rest in the 'revolution' of the later eighteenth century. Beteille

specifically locates the argument in Tocqueville's work and links it to

Tocqueville's own personal position as torn between the two worlds.

 

The first and in some ways still the most outstanding contrast between the hierarchical

social order of the past and the emerging social order with its commitment to equality

was the one made by Alexis de Tocqueville. Tocqueville's contrast between aristocracy

 

 

287

 

and democracy is not confined to two modes of political organization; it extends to

patterns of social distinction, forms of religious experience and consciousness, and

types of aesthetic sensibility. Although born a few years after the French Revolution,

he came from an aristocratic family, one which had suffered by it, and he spoke of the

life and ideals of the aristocracy with the insight of personal knowledge. On the other

hand, democracy still lay largely in the future, although the promise of that future

infused his writing with an astonishingly vivid quality. (1983: 74)

 

Or again, Beteille writes

 

Alexis de Tocqueville was the first to bring out the full significance of the normative

order of the new society that was emerging in the United States. A European, steeped

in the traditions of aristocracy, he could not but be impressed by the pervasive influence

of the principle of equality in every sphere of life. The idea that people should be

permanently divided into ranks invested with unequal rights and obligations was,

according to Tocqueville, contrary to the spirit of American society; it was of equality

and not hierarchy that custom religion all spoke in one voice. Tocqueville

maintained further that the spirit of equality would come to prevail over the spirit of

hierarchy, in Europe , and in the world as a whole. (1977: 151)

 

THE SECOND DISTINCTION: HARMONIC AND

DISHARMONIC SYSTEMS

 

Beteille is not content to stop here and is again guided by Tocqueville to

search for a more complex formulation. He argues that dichotomized thinking,

except in terms of 'ideal types' is dangerously misleading. Thus he writes,

 

I find it false to represent the opposition between equality and inequality as a contrast

between two societies in two different parts of the world. On the contrary, each society

is an arena within which the two interplay, and if we fail to examine this interplay

within societies, the comparisons we make between societies will be shallow and

misleading. (1983: 38)

 

He praises Tocqueville himself for breaking Out of just such dichotomized

thinking.

 

The attraction of Tocqueville's work lies in his refusal to be a prisoner of his own

dichotomy. While he dwells at great length on the opposite natures of aristocratic and        -

democratic societies, he leaves room for considering the contradictions "-]thin each

type of society. (ibid.: 41)

 

Indeed some of Beteille's best insights come out of his recognition of the

contradictions within systems.

 

     This uneasiness at the over-simple dichotomizing of' Past: Present, and

West: Rest is shown in certain passages where Beteille questions some of his

own earlier assumptions about the 'hierarchical' nature of 'the West' before

the eighteenth century. He writes that 'The more closely one examines the

 

 

 

288

 

old order in the West the less plausible the argument appears that it knew

nothing of equality as a value' (ibid.: 43). ',"his is a summary of an earlier

passage where he points to one contradiction, also noted by Tocqueville

 

It is clear that equality as an ideal and a value was never wholly alien to Western

civilization even when its organization \\/as most elaborately hierarchical. No institution

within that civilization was more hierarchical than the Catholic church, and indeed

the concept of hierarchy 1, in its meaning a Christian concept. Tocqueville

recognized and noted this-, at the same time he did not fall to point out that 'Christianity,

which has declared that all men are equal in the sight of God, will not refuse to

acknowledge that all citizens are equal in the eye of the law.' It Is as if a value and an

ideal that had lain dormant under a hierarchical organization came into its own when

external conditions favoured its awakening, and then invested these external conditions

with a new significance. (ibid.: 41-2)

 

Thus Beteille picks up Tocqueville's idea that all systems are mixed: that

I pure' hierarchy or equality only exists as an ideal type, and that in reality

any society at any point in time will be the result of a dynamic and moving

equilibrium between incompatible and ever-varying forces. Systems are

neither static nor consistent and Beteille has often pointed this out in relation

to the Indian past.

 

      In trying to proceed beyond unsatisfactory dichotomies, Beteille has

proposed a distinction between two kinds of social system which he calls

'harmonic' and 'disharmonic' He defines a 'harmonic' system as follows: it is

 

one in which there is consistency between the normative order and the existential

order: society is divided into groups which are placed high and low, and the divisions

and their ordering are considered as right, proper and desirable or as a part of the

natural scheme of things. (ibid.: 54)

 

He then describes India as a good example of such a system; there is a premise

and a practice of inequality, there is no fundamental contradiction (ibid.: 57-

64).

 

     A second form of 'harmonic' system can be envisaged 'in which there is

equality in both principle and practice'. Beteille does not give any worked

examples of such a harmonic system, though he does consider the question

generally (1977: ch. 7). The most obvious examples are some of the very

simplest hunter - gatherer bands (Woodburn 1982), but once mankind

established settled agrarian civilizations it is difficult to see examples. We

know too much to believe that communism, where all are in theory equal but

some more equal than others, has produced durable instances. 'America' as

encountered by Tocqueville came closer than most instances, for a time, to

this condition, as Tocqueville himself noted. In America Tocqueville found a

land which had explicitly enthroned the premise of equality, rather than of

inequality. It made it a central tenet that man was born free and equal. This

was still a peculiar way of looking at things and Tocqueville consequently

 

 

 

289

 

noted that 'No novelty in the United States struck me more vividly during

my stay there than the equality of conditions' (Tocqueville 1968a: 1, 5).

Equality, or democracy as he often called it, became the key to understanding

America. 'So the more I studied American society, the more clearly I saw

equality of conditions as the creative element from which each particular

fact derived, and all my observations  constantly returned to this nodal point'

(ibid.). There had been some early attempts to take inequality over from the

Old World, but they had failed. 'Laws were made there to establish the

hierarchy of ranks, but it was soon seen that the soil of America absolutely

rejected a territorial aristocracy' (ibid: 1, 37).

 

    Beteille does not stop here, however, for he suggests a further distinction,

that is the idea of 'disharmonic' systems which 'by contrast show[s] a lack

of consistency between the existential and the normative orders'. One form

is where 'the norm of equality is contradicted by the persuasive existence of

inequality'. This seems to characterize much of modern 'western' civilization,

including America in its later history, where 'Despite the idealization of

equality, the class structure continues to be an important part of Western

social reality, some would say its most important part' (1983: 76). Beteille

quotes Raymond Aron to the effect that 'Modem industrial societies are both

egalitarian in aspiration and hierarchical in organization' and adds the comment

that 'Modem societies are in this sense disharmonic: there is in them a lack of

consistency between the normative and the existential order' (1977: 15 1). The

clash between ideology and practice, and even within the ideology, is shown

even more clearly when the 'West' dominated much of Asia and elsewhere.

 

Those who trace the historical conditions of the emergence of homo equalis in the West

generally overlook the adventures of the same homo equalis abroad. As if the destruction

of aboriginal society in Australia and America, the enslavement and brutal use of millions

of Blacks, or the imposition of the most unequal conditions between European and

natives throughout Asia took place in another epoch or on another planet. (1983: 52-3)

 

This is written with feeling by someone brought up in the shadow of the Raj.

 

     We may summarize the theoretical structure which Beteille has suggested

in a diagram (see Fig. 1).

 

A DISHARMONIC SYSTEM IN THE 'WEST'

 

Beteille is in many ways most interested in the 'disharmonic' case (D), where

a civilization proclaims equality but practises inequality, for this, in essence,

is the modern situation.

 

The great paradox of the modem world is that everywhere men attach themselves to

the principle of equality and everywhere, in their own lives as well as in the lives of

others, they encounter the presence of inequality. The more strongly they attach

themselves to the principles or the ideology of equality the more oppressive the reality

becomes. (1977: 1)

 

 

 

290

 

INSERT FIGURE HERE

 

 

                         FIG. 1. Four types of stratification

 

 

When did this contradiction emerge and what are its deeper features? Here

Beteille can only set us on the path.

 

     Beteille notes at several places that within the general harmonic ancien

regime of western Europe before the French Revolution, there seems to have

been something unusual about England which hints at 'disharmony'. For

instance he notes that England seems to have been different in certain respects.

 

Moreover, the system varied considerably from one region to another even within

Western Europe not only in its formal arrangement but also in its course of growth,

maturity and decay. The contrast between France and England-the 'exceptional case

of England'-is a commonplace of medieval European history. (1983: 65)

 

Or again Beteille writes that

 

Even between France and England, neighbours who shared many things in common,

there were important differences. The nobility never acquired in England the array of

privileges it enjoyed in France, and English historians frequently point to the antiquity

of their own traditions of equality.

 

He continues, however, by qualifying this remark by noting that 'for all its

distinctiveness, England also developed a social hierarchy, many elements of

which lasted longer there than in other West European countries' (ibid.).

Beteille's hints of an unusually early disharmonic system in England lead us

straight back to Tocqueville.

 

 

 

291

 

On his first visit to England in 1833 Tocqueville wrote as follows:

 

But what distinguishes it [the aristocracy of England] from all others is the ease, with

which it has opened its ranks ... with great riches, anybody could hope to enter into

the ranks of the aristocracy. Furthermore since everybody could hope to become rich,

especially in such a mercantile country as England, a peculiar position arose in that

their privileges, which raised such feeling against the aristocrats of other countries,

were the thing that most attached the English to theirs.... The English aristocracy in

feelings and prejudices resembles all the aristocracies of the world, but it is not in the

least founded on birth, that inaccessible thing, but on wealth that everyone can acquire,

and this one difference makes it stand, while the others succumb either to the people

or to the King. (1968b: 43)

 

Thus England combined very great de facto differences, with few de jure

privileges.

 

    As Tocqueville left England he summarized many of his impressions.

 

In England an illustrious name is a great advantage . . . but in general one can say that

the aristocracy is founded on wealth, a thing which may be acquired, and not on birth

which cannot. From this it results that one can clearly see in England where real

aristocracy begins, but it is impossible to say where it ends.

 

Furthermore, the real difference can be pinned down on to one word.

 

The difference between England and France in this matter turns on the examination

of a single word in each language. 'Gentleman' and 'gentilhomme' evidently have

the same derivation, but 'gentleman' in England is applied to every well-educated

man whatever his birth, while is France gentilhomme applies only to a noble by birth.

The meaning of these two words of common origin has been so transformed by the

different social climates of the two countries that today they simply cannot be

translated, at least without recourse to a periphrasis. This grammatical observation is

more illuminating than many long arguments. (ibid.: 51-2)

 

The situation partly arose from the commercial nature of England, whose

wealth could be acquired from sources other than land and hence a parallel

I aristocracy' constantly emerged and challenged the older families.

 

In this way an aristocracy of wealth was soon established and, as the world became

more civilized and more opportunities of gaining wealth presented themselves, it

increased, whereas the old aristocracy, for the same reasons, continually lost ground.

(ibid.: 104)

 

The consequences were status competition and uncertainty, a constant pre-

occupation with small marks of difference and attempts to outdo others.

Paradoxically this meant that in the middle of the nineteenth century England

was more snobbish than France.’ The French wish not to have superiors. The

English wish to have inferiors. The Frenchman constantly raises his eyes

above him with anxiety. The Englishman lowers his beneath him with

 

 

 

292

 

satisfaction' (ibid.: 60). Ranks still existed in England, but they were confused.

'When birth alone, independent of wealth, decides a man's class, each knows

exactly where he stands on the social ladder. He neither seeks to rise nor

fears to fall.' But when 'an aristocracy of wealth takes the place of one of

birth, this is no longer the case.' This is because

 

As a man's social worth is not ostensibly and permanently fixed by his birth, but

varies infinitely with his wealth. ranks -Still exist, but it cannot be seen clearly at first

sight by whom the\, are represented. The immediate result is an unspoken warfare

between all the citizens. One Idea tries by a thousand dodges to infiltrate, in fact or in

appearance. among those above them ']'he others are constantly trying to push back

these usurper.,, of their rights. Or rather the same man plays both parts ... (1968a: Il,

731-2)

 

This was one of the reasons the English were so guarded with each other:

they found it difficult, especially if they met away from England, to know

who they were dealing with (ibid.: 11, 73 1). It was also an explanation of why

it was so difficult to envisage a revolution in England. De Tocqueville believed

that 'The English aristocracy can therefore never arouse those violent hatreds

felt by the middle and lower classes against the nobility in France where the

nobility is an exclusive caste . . .'In England, 'The English aristocracy has a

hand in everything; it is open to everyone; and everyone who wishes to abolish

it or attack it as a body, would have a hard task to define the object of his

onslaught' (1968b: 52). One of de Tocqueville's greatest puzzles, taking up a

theme from Montesquieu, was why England had become so different. (2)

 

     De Tocqueville suggested that out of a common European feudalism, that

is the odd mixture which arose out of a decomposing Roman civilization and

Germanic customs, the subsequent paths of continental Europe and England

were different. He started with the premise that there had been very little

difference between the parts of western Europe in the Dark Ages. The system

which emerged in about the ninth century covered the whole of western and

central Europe (ibid.: 2). Then came the invasion of England by de

Tocqueville's Norman ancestors. At this point, Normandy and much of France,

as well as most of the Continent, were identical to England. Yet this identical

system produced contrary results. By the seventeenth century there was a

great divergence. 'Everywhere on the Continent at the beginning of the

seventeenth century absolute monarchies stood triumphantly on the ruins of

the feudal or oligarchic freedom of the Middle Ages' (1968a: 1, 52-3). Yet in

England,

 

Shutting your eyes to the old names and forms, you will find from the seventeenth

century the feudal-system substantially abolished, classes which overlap, nobility of

birth set on one side, aristocracy thrown open, wealth as the source of power, equality

before the law, office open to all, liberty of the press, publicity of debate.... Seventeenth-

century England was already a quite modem nation, which has merely preserved in its

heart, and as it were embalmed, some relics of the Middle Ages. (1956: 21)

 

 

 

293

 

In these ways it diverged dramatically from what happened elsewhere in

Europe. What then is the great difference according to de Tocqueville?

 

It was far less its Parliament, its liberty, its publicity, its jury, which in fact rendered

the England of that date so unlike the rest of Europe than a feature still more exclusive

and more powerful. England was the only country in which the system of caste had

been not changed but effectively destroyed. The nobles and the middle classes in

England followed together the same courses of business, entered the same professions,

and, what is much more significant, intermarried. (ibid.: 89)

 

The fact that inequalities on the basis of birth had been abolished, or had

never properly arisen, in England, did not mean that there was little inequality.

Ironically, the aristocracy was flourishing in eighteenth -century England while

it was decaying all over Europe.

 

This gradual impoverishment of the nobles was seen more or less not only in France

but in all parts of the continent where the feudal system, as in France, disappeared

without being replaced by a new form of aristocracy. Among the German peoples, who

bordered the Rhine, this decay was everywhere visible and much noticed. The contrary

was only met with in England. In England the old noble families which still existed

had not only preserved, but also had largely increased their wealth.... (ibid.: 86)

 

Thus one found in England, 'apparent equality, real privileges of wealth,

greater perhaps than in any country in the world' (1968b: 79). Of course they

proclaimed the universal rights and equality of men. But what did these consist

of? The English have left the poor but two rights: 'that of obeying the same

laws as the rich, and that of standing on an equality with them if they can

obtain equal wealth' (ibid.: 78).

 

    This clash between a de jure situation where everyone in theory was equal,

but some definitely ended up as richer and more powerful, was made more

difficult to bear by the loss of religious faith. In most societies, the poor

could reconcile themselves to their position by realizing that there was no

alternative: they were born into a fixed social position. Or again, in many

religions their position was determined by their activities in previous lives. It

was not their fault, a result of their fecklessness or inability. Even Christianity

had provided the solace that even if this life was one of poverty, there would

be recompense in eternity. The rich would find it virtually impossible to get

through the eye of the needle into heaven. The poor and meek would inherit

the earth, and heaven too. Yet as faith evaporated, men and women were

faced not only with physical misery, but no consolation prize in the after life.

Thus inequalities were particularly hard to bear 'in an epoch when our view

into another world has become dimmer, and the miseries of this world become

more visible and seem more intolerable' (1948: 84). The English case is

relatively familiar to many of us since, to a certain extent, it is part of the air

we breathe now, through its extension to America and Europe over the last

three hundred years. Through de Tocqueville's analysis, this third case, the

 

 

 

294

 

origins and spread of the major disharmonic form which now dominates the

world, become less mysterious.

 

A DISHARMONIC SYSTEM IN THE 'EAST'

 

Beteille also considers briefly the last logical possibility (A), that is a

'disharmonic' system in which 'people practise equality while professing its

opposite'. Yet he excludes this category from consideration 'as being remote

from historical experience' (, 1983: 54). In fact, in small-scale instances, it is

probably fairly common. One variant is to be found, for instance, in the area

where I do anthropological fieldwork in the central Himalayas. The 'Gurungs'

were at one stage transhumant shepherds and hunter-gatherers and, on the

whole, their ideology and practice was towards the egalitarian end of the

continuum. During the last three hundred or more years they have gradually

been absorbed into a hierarchical model based on the Hindu caste system.

There is a marked tension, however, for while the ideology is often explicitly

hierarchical, with 'Untouchable' groups, ritual impurity and so on, in practice

the interpersonal relations and distribution of wealth have manifested a

considerable amount of de facto equality (Macfarlane 1976, 1993). No doubt

many similar examples could be found on the interface between tribal and

caste societies.

 

    Here, however, I would like to conclude by considering a civilization which

has for at least a thousand years manifested a notable tension or contradiction

between an ideology of inequality and a practice of much de facto equality.

This is the puzzling case of Japan. Although the following account is necessarily

schematized and over-simplified, it is worth exploring briefly the one large-

scale case which seems to fit the last of Beteille's four major ideal types.

At the ideological or cultural level of interpersonal relations, Japan has

long been and remains today one of the most hierarchical or inegalitarian

societies ever known. We are often told that equal relationships are

impossible in Japan. Japan is and always has been a 'vertical' society, where

every relationship is of an inferior to a superior. This is built into the

language, etiquette and all of life. Chie Nakane's work epitomizes this view.

'The relationship between two individuals of upper and lower status is the

basis of the structural principle of Japanese society.' 'In fact, in Japan it is

very difficult to form and maintain the sort of voluntary association found

so often in western societies, in that it does not have the basis or frame of

existing horizontal personal relations.' 'The golden rule is that the junior

man should invariably carry out any order from his immediate superior, for

this immediate link between the two men is the source of the existence of

the junior man in the organization.' 'The core of the Japanese family, ancient

and modern, is the parent-child relationship, not that between husband and

wife. So the family today also reflects the predominance of vertical

relationships' (Nakane 1973: 44, 62, 55, 133).

 

 

 

 295

 

Although Nakane is the most systematic in her analysis of the vertical nature

of Japanese society, others are in broad agreement. Robert Bellah wrote,

 

The particular characteristic of the Japanese institutional system was its strong

emphasis on the vertical axis and relatively small reliance oil horizontal ties. That is,

the institutional structure was held together largely through ties of loyalty between

superior and inferior. (1957: 55)

 

Ruth Benedict had written earlier that 'Whatever one's age, one's position in

the hierarchy depends on whether one is male or female. The Japanese woman

walks behind her husband and has a lower status' (1967: 37). Takie Lebra

explains that Japanese 'siblings are also hierarchically graded in a strikingly

elaborate system based on seniority. One is a junior brother or a senior brother

vis-a-vis every other brother, unless the two happen to have entered the group

at the same time' (1976: 179).

 

     Indeed language itself makes an -equal relationship impossible. As Paul

Bohannan noted, all Japanese verb endings must denote relative rank (1969:

43). and hence, for example as Robert Smith, quoting Miyoshi, observed

 

In such interaction between young male equals, each speaks as though the listener

were his inferior [that is, both use less polite speech]; between female equals, each as

though the listener were her superior [that is, both use more polite speech]; between

male and female equals, she speaks with [deference], he without it .... (1983: 75)

 

It is difficult, in one sense, to conceive of a less egalitarian society.

 

    Yet, in practice, the pervasive inequality is situational; a person is not

intrinsically unequal by virtue of birth (unless he or she happens to be a

foreigner or a member of the discriminated croup, the burakamin). Hence,

many see Japan as one of the few truly egalitarian societies, with little

permanent ranking, orders, castes or classes, and with very considerable

opportunities for social mobility. This was noted long ago by Basil Hall

Chamberlain.

 

Some have used the word 'caste' to denote these divisions-, but the term is inappropriate,

as there exists no impassable barrier between the different classes. nor yet anything

approaching to Indian caste prejudice. The feeling only resembles that to which we

are accustomed in England, if indeed it is as strong.

 

Chamberlain comments, 'And how this moderation makes for happiness!

The rich not being blatant, the poor are not abject-, in fact, though poverty

exists, pauperism does not. A genuine spirit of equality pervades society'

(1971: 95, 449).

 

The fact that Japan is at the opposite extreme from a 'caste' society has

been echoed by anthropologists. For example, some years ago A.L. Kroeber

wrote that 'Japan is often cited as a land of caste', but believed that 'this

was true to perhaps the same degree as of medieval Europe', and believed

 

 

 

296

 

that 'occupational elaboration and integration with religion remained vague'

(Kroeber 1935). More recently, Chie Nakane. who has also worked on the

fringes of a caste society, in Assam, writes that the general ideology of

Japan shows itself to be 'completely~. the opposite of the caste ideology, in

which division of labour and the interdependence of groups are the basic

principles of social organization . ton In ,i caste society groups are formed of

homogeneous elements. while in Japan they consist of heterogeneous

elements' (1973: 105).

 

     The contradiction is captured by Edwin 0. Reischauer. 'Status is

vastly important. But i of' (:lass and actual class differences are both

extremely weak-. In essential ways, Japan today has a very egalitarian

society-more so in fact than those of the United States and many European

countries.' He believes that this is partly related to the strength of the small

group. "Otherwise, groups associations, by emphasizing discrete hierarchical

relationships and reducing lateral contacts with groups of similar function

and status, play down class feelings as these are known in the West.' He

concludes that 'Japanese society is rent by no sharp cleavage. There is virtually

no great inherited wealth and very little degrading poverty' (1988: 150, 152,

174)., It is perhaps this which makes the Japanese themselves uncomfortable

with the label of 'vertical society'. 'There-- is a popular, conventional theory

that Japan is a vertical society. Nothing could be more mistaken. Japan is a

circular society.' Michiro Matsumoto himself, visiting the land of equality

reports that 'I learned the hard way that it is the American society that is

intrinsically vertical' (1988: 121, 126).

 

    Japan is thus famously a 'small group society'. Within the group there

are vertical differences, but between the groups there is a great deal of equality.

There are no fixed and permanent strata, just powerful internally stratified

entities. This is described by Nakane as follows: 'There is no obvious status

group formed by masters or landlords, excluding peasants: on the contrary, a

functional group was formed by landlord and tenant, master and servant, and

the master or superior was always one of them in the same group' (1973:

152). This explains why, for instance, there was no distinct aristocracy or

ruling class. As Lebra, citing Hasegawa, puts it, 'the aristocracy in Japan,

compared with its European, Chinese, and Indian counterparts, has formed a

less distinct cultural elite, less separate from the working mass' (1976: 83).

It is thus impossible to speak of the 'upper class' or the 'ruling class'. (3)

 

    Thus what is curious about Japan is that the whole society;. is based on the

premise of situational inequality, yet de facto there is little ranking of groups.

It teaches us that there is a strong middle position between the two extremes

represented in the usual sociological models. Such situational inequality see,-ns

perfectly compatible with advanced industrialism. Thus Japan is, depending

on how one looks at it, the most egalitarian, or the least egalitarian of societies.

At the cultural level of language, kinship, gender and age, there is hierarchy

everywhere; no one is equal. At the level of formal stratification in terms of

 

297

 

class, caste and wealth, there is surprisingly great equality for most. We thus

have a system that combines two apparently contradictory principles-

extreme inequality and extreme equality.

 

     We can understand the situation a little better if we look very briefly at

Japanese history. I shall do so here by using one source alone, that is the

multi.- volume Cambridge History of Japan, which has recently been published

(see Macfarlane 1997). Between the twelfth and late sixteenth centuries, it

would appear that Japan was an unusually 'open' society. It is difficult to

speak of castes, classes or even estates. Thus Barbara Ruch writes that 'there

was as yet no particular differentiation among an artisan, manufacturer, peddler,

merchant, or a worker engaged in providing services, except perhaps in their

economic success or failure' (Yamamura 1990: 514). Neither in theory nor

practice was there rigidity in the large urban and commercial sector. The

same was true among the large numbers of those who worked on the land.

We may note, for example, the absence of slavery in the normal sense of

the word, or even of unfree peasants. The situation was complicated because

there were numerous different sub-groups 'based on a complicated status

system', with each group having a different name 'indicating the group's

relative degree of freedom or subordination'. The largest group, that is the

normal workers on the land, what Japanese historians term 'peasants', were

relatively free. Oyama Kyohel writes that 'from observations of the various

representative shoen [landed proprietors], it is clear that the shoen peasants

could act fairly freely and that on occasion they both allied with and resisted

the jito [estate manager] and shoen (Yamamura 1990: 120). Thus the same

author concludes that 'the medieval peasant was basically a 'freeman' (jijymin)

(ibid.: 121). A 'free' peasantry of this kind is unusual, probably only to be

found in parts of western Europe and Japan at this early date. That it remained

free in England and Japan over the centuries that followed is of great

importance.

 

    As in so many features the reforms of the early Tokugawa seemed to

change all this.' They aimed at imposing, for the first time, a rigid system of

social stratification. The actual fact of stratification seems at first sight to

have destroyed the openness of the medieval period. The closure was meant

to prevent all kinds of mobility, not only social, but occupational and

geographic. Thus, for example, Gilbert Rozman writes that 'Peasants were

barred from entering the samurai class, and in principle, from moving to the

cities, from switching to non-agricultural pursuits, and from selling or using

their land as they might see fit' (Jansen 1989: 516). Yet the policy seems to

have been fairly ineffective. Donald Shively writes that 'From the early Edo

[Tokugawa] period, the government recognized the order of the four classes

as samurai (shi), farmer (no), craftsmen (ko) and merchant (sho) (quoted in

Hall 1991). But 'Although Confucianists often spoke of this class order, it

was never given a legal basis, and its artificiality and imprecision must be

kept in mind'(Hall 1991: 708). The outward signs of the failure to create and

 

 

 

 298

 

maintain rigidity are numerous. In relation to geographic mobility it failed;

there was massive mobility. Furthermore, there was much movement between

occupations, with many farmers having bi-occupations. This fluidity was

shown in externals such as dress. As Susan Hanley observes, 'one would

expect to find that dress varied by class and income in a highly stratified

society' yet 'what is remarkable for Tokugawa Japan is how similar the basic

cut of the clothing was for each Thus we are told that the 'daily wear

of men of both the samurai and merchant classes was remarkably similar in

basic style . . . dress in fact was gradually being standardized and class

differences minimized (Hall I 1 91)1: 69"1-3). The blending emerged as a result

of a number of factors, some of which may be briefly mentioned.

 

     Following Shively, we learn that it was impossible to maintain the

supposed distinction between the two classes of craftsmen and merchants.

'In practice, no attempt was made to distinguish craftsmen from merchants:

both were treated as a single group' (Hall 1991: 709). Secondly, within each

supposed 'class' there were great differences in actual wealth and hence

instability was introduced into the classification system. We are told that

'Bushi [warrior class] included not only the shogun and the daimyo [higher

lords] but also the humble servants of samurai. Farmers ranged from rich

landowners and village headmen to tenants and agricultural servants' (ibid.:

711). Thirdly, the distinctions between the samurai and the rest were soon

blurred. For instance, while 'Intermarriage between samurai and commoners

was considered inappropriate', in fact 'bushi were permitted, not uncommonly,

to take commoner wives' and hence 'A kind of cultural levelling occurred I

(ibid.: 7 11). The mechanism of adoption added to this fluidity; many rich

commoners' children were adopted into the samurai ranks. The alliance

between ancient blood and new wealth, which was a distinct characteristic of

late medieval and early modern England, was also common in Japan.

 

    Thus there was a growing mingling and mixing of groups as wealth

increased. The tendency of money to undermine the supposedly separate ranks

is summarized by a number of authors and Rozman cites Kozo Yamamura to

the effect that under the pressure of economic necessity, class distinctions

became 'virtually nonexistent' (Jansen 1989: 531). Everything became

purchasable on the market-including rank. For instance, as early as 1783,

'the han [lordly domains] provided the convenience of a price list for status,

from 50 ryo for wearing a sword to 620 ryo for full warrior standing' (ibid.:

79). This was merely regularizing what was already in place; the possibility

of exchanging wealth for status, the hallmark of the stratification system of

modern societies. All this helps to explain why at the Meiji restoration the

remains of the system of separate estates evaporated so very quickly. A

summary also captures the gap between the formal rules and the practice. 'If

we look only at how Japanese society was supposed to operate, we will find

a rigid class society in place throughout the Tokugawa period.' On the other

hand, as Hanley writes, in practice. 'Japan lost its class distinctions far more

 

299

 

quickly and are more thoroughly than England did.' It seems very likely that 'much of the reason has to be the blurring of class lines before the Meiji Restoration' (Hall 1991: 703-4)

 

SYNTHESIS

 

I have suggested that de Tocqueville was Beteille's unacknowledged mentor, helping to set his intellectual agenda and providing guidance on a number of the deepest issues. His openly acknowledged inspiration was, however, Max Weber, who not only reinforced the need for comparison and contrast in all social scientific research, but also encouraged Beteille to develop 'ideal type' analysis. Beteille's ideal types of harmonic and disharmonic are valuable because they show that while remaining 'pure' in principle, an ideal type can contain within itself a structural contradiction or opposition. 'Disharmonic' systems are essentially unstable; they contain a clash of ideology and practice Of course there are even more complicated contradictions than those discussed here, for the ideology itself, as Beteille frequently acknowledges in relation to both 'India' and the 'West', is usually founded on contradictions. But for the present we can limit ourselves to a simple model. The conclusions emerging from combining de Tocqueville, Beteille and a brief discussion of the Japanese case can be summarised in a further diagram (see Fig.2).

 

INSERT FIG. 2 HERE

 

               FIG.2. Instances of the Four Systems of Stratification

 

 

 

300

 

    Of course, none of these cases is fixed and like the famous instance

documented by Edmund Leach in Highland Burma, they swing back and

forth along both poles over time (Leach 1964). What is intriguing, however,

is to see in the two cases analysed more full\' here, England and Japan.

how there are both fluctuations and continuities. Likewise, if there is any

truth in this analysis, it helps to explain why both Japanese and western

observers feel a mixed sense of familiarity and difference when they

contemplate or experience each other's civilizations. They recognize an

affinity, another disharmonic or contradictory system, a good deal of equality

in practice. Yet they also sense a deep difference. There is indeed a gulf and

in certain ways the two civilizations are inversions or mirror images of

each other. The two different disharmonic systems are both alike and unlike

at the same time.

 

    At a wider level, it is worth being reminded that the 'Us' and "Them'

dichotomy. which Louis Dumont among others exemplifies, is unsatisfactory. (5)

We all experience It and nearly all of us can see the 'Other' as a complete

reversal of ourselves. Hence to see 'India' as part of the 'Orient', as the

reverse of ourselves is tempting, as discussion of 'Orientalism' has shown.

The simple bifurcation of Homo Hierarchicus and Homo Equalis, made not

only into a geographic contrast, but also an historical one, the past being

'hierarchical' until the sudden emergence of 'modernity', is very tempting.

Most of us stand here and now, and we see 'them', whether in other

civilizations or past ages, as very different and there is always enough

substance in the view to give it an initial plausibility.

 

     What is rarer is to proceed to the second step, that is to see that in both

'Us' and 'Them', whether this is conceived of geographically or temporally,

there are contradictions. It needs a special sort of person, living in special

conditions, to do so. Here we may be able to guess at something which unites

de Tocqueville and Beteille. Their experience means that they lived in two

worlds, with an allegiance to both. For somewhat different, but overlapping,

reasons de Tocqueville and Beteille sense the attractions of both hierarchy

and equality, and even more importantly sense that a pure state of one or the

other is rare. They know from their own experience that there is disharmony,

a telling word in Beteille's formulation, or contradiction, in which ideology

and practice clash. They are thus able to move beyond the first step of

recognizing contrast to the deeper recognition of similarity with difference;

that is to the recognition of dialectical tensions and the clash of contradictory

forces which gives their work a much more realistic approximation to the

movement of societies in history.

 

     Because of his personal and structural position Beteille has been one of

the few recent writers to have significantly advanced our understanding of

equality a,-id inequality. In this respect, as in others, we are grateful to him

for his clear, insightful and beautifully coherent writing which reveals so

much about our predicament. Like de Tocqueville facing 'America', Beteille

 

 

 

301

 

shows us in an indirect way the struggles of an upright and sensitive man,

deeply imbued with his mother's love of truth and Gandhian ideals of equality,

trying to come to terms with the excitement, but also the hypocrisies, dangers

and scarcely hidden injuries of the proclaimed 'equalizing' mission of the

West. Like other major thinkers he stands between worlds and helps to

illuminate our options.

 

 

ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS

 

I am grateful to Ramachandra Guha and Jonathan Parry for their insightful

comments on an earlier draft of this article which have helped me to

reformulate the argument

 

NOTES

 

I For the first instalment of Beteille's autobiography, which will clarify issues in

his background, see Beteille (1997).

2 Montesquieu's arguments, and an expanded version of this account of de

Tocqueville's theories, will be given in my book provisionally titled The Riddle

of the World.

3 Of course this does not mean that there are not tensions, for example frequent

.peasant' revolts, see for instance Vlastos (1986.)

4 The Tokugawa shogunate, also known as the Edo period (after the capital city of

Edo or Tokyo as it is now known), was from 1603 to 1868.

5 For a critique of Dumont (1970,1977), see Macfarlane (1992) and Beteille (1993).

 

 

REFERENCES

 

Bellah, Robert N., (1957). Tokugawa Religion: The Values of Pre-Industrial Japan.

Glencoe, Ill.: Free Press.

Benedict, Ruth, (1967). The Chrysanthemum and the Sword: Patterns of Japanese

Culture. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.

Beteille, Andre, (1965). Caste, Class, and Power: Changing Patterns of Stratification

in a Tanjore Village, London: University of California Press.

(ed.), (1969). Social Inequality; Selected Readings. London: Penguin Books.

(1977). Inequality among Men. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

(1983). The Idea of Natural Inequality and Other Essays. New Delhi: Oxford

University Press.

(19()3). 'Equality and Universality'. Cambridge Anthropology 17(l): 1-12.

(1997). 'My Two Grandmothers'. Civil Lines, 3. New Delhi: Orient Longman.

Bohannan, Paul, (1969). Social Anthropology. New York: Holt, Rinehart and

Winston.

Chamberlain, Basil Hall, (1971) [1904]. Japanese Things: Being Notes on Various

Subjects Connected with Japan. Tokyo: Tuttle.

 

 

302

 

de Tocqueville, Alexis, (1861). Memoir, Letters, and Remains of Alexis de Tocqueville.

London: Macmillan, 2 vols.

-, (1948) [1893]. The Recollections of Alexis de Tocqueville, (ed.) J. P. Mayer,

trans. Alexander Teixeira de Mattos. London: Harvill Press.

-, (1956) [18561. L'Ancien Regime, trans. M.W. Patterson. Oxford: Basin

Blackwell.

- (1968a) [1835. 1840] Democracy in America, trans. George Lawrence.

London: Fontana, 2 vols.

-, (1968b). Journeys to England and Ireland, (ed.), J. P. Mayer, trans. George

Lawrence and J. P. Mayer. New York: Anchor Books.

Dumont, Louis, (1970). Homo Hierarchicus: The Caste System and Its Implications.

London: Paladin.

--, (1977). From Mandeville to Marx: The Genesis and Triumph of Economic

Ideology. Chicago: Chicago University Press.

Hall, John Whitney (ed.), (1991). The Cambridge History of Japan: Early Modern

Japan, vol. 4. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Jansen, Marius B. (ed.), (1989). The Cambridge History of Japan: The Nineteenth

Century, vol. 5. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Kroeber, A. L., (1935). 'Caste', in Encyclopedia of the Social Science (ed.) E. R. A.

Seligman. New York: Macmillan.

Leach, Edmund, (1964). Political Systems of Highland Burma: A Study of Kachin

Social Structure. London: Athlone Press.

Lebra, Takie Sugiyama, (1976). Japanese Patterns of Behaviour Honolulu: University

of Hawaii Press.

Macfarlane, Alan, (1976). Resources and Population: A Study of the Gurungs of  Central

Nepal. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

-, (,1992). 'Louis Dumont and the Origins of Individualism'. Cambridge

Anthropology 16, no. 1.

--, (1993). Appendix C to Bernard Pignede, The Gurungs: A Himalayan

Population of Nepal, trans, edited and annotated by Alan Macfarlane and Sarah

Harrison. Kathmandu: Ratna Pustak Bhandar.

(1997). "Japan" in an English Mirror: A Review of vols. 2-5 of the Cambridge

History of Japan'. Modern Asian Studies, 31(41): 763-806.

Matsumoto, Michiro, (1988). The Unspoken Way; Haragei, Silence in Japanese

Business and Society. Tokyo: Kodansha.

Nakane, Chie, (1973). Japanese Society. London: Penguin Books.

Reischauer, Edwin 0., (1988). The Japanese Today: Change and Continuity. Tokyo:

Tuttle.

Smith, Robert J., (1983). Japanese Society; Tradition, Self and the Social Order-

Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Vlastos, Stephen, (1986). Peasant Protests and Uprisings in Tokugawa Japan.

Berkeley: University of California Press.

Woodburn, James, (1982). 'Egalitarian Societies'. Man (n.s.)17:431-51

Yamamura. Kozo (ed.), (1990). Cambridge History of Japan.- Medieval Japan, 3.

Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.